Based on this information, the woman can decide whether she would like to obtain further, and likely more accurate, information. This usually involves invasively obtaining a sample from the placenta or amniotic fluid. Some decide to have this, some do not. And some will be informed their fetus will be born with a chromosomal trisomy.
Of these, most will terminate. We don't know how many women do this in Australia as data is not kept in a consistent way between states. But in Britain, a 2009 paper gave the termination rate for detected cases of Down syndrome as 92 per cent.
The ethical question is whether such screening, and ending those pregnancies where a condition is identified, is acceptable.
Making choicesFor the most part, pregnant women wish to remain pregnant. While it is one thing for a male parent of a surrogate baby to claim, after the fact, that he would have requested a termination, the decisions faced by pregnant women are much less frivolous.
Screening is primarily about facilitating choice through information provision; it's not about putting women on a conveyor belt to termination. Because our society has differing views on conditions such as Down syndrome, some couples wish to access information to inform their decision-making in pregnancy.
Some wish to have this information to help adjust to life with a child who has a disability; others use it to plan for birth; while others might choose to end the pregnancy and try again.
This latter decision is not necessarily borne from inherent prejudice, but a recognition that certain conditions may mean their child could have profound problems. Ending a pregnancy is not something taken lightly, whatever the circumstances.
The moral status of the fetus is an intractable issue in our society. Nevertheless, termination is possible at certain points in pregnancy and for certain reasons.
Using knowledge wiselyStill, the acceptability of both the offer to screen for abnormalities in pregnancy, and the action taken on the basis of its results, should not detract from several important considerations.
Women or couples must make a choice about screening and potential termination with access to full and balanced information. It must also be made clear that undergoing any test is a choice, not an expectation.
Women need to have time to think about their choices, which are often difficult and made under a time pressure.
We must not use screening as an excuse for withdrawing practical or psychological support for people who choose to continue a pregnancy that will lead to the birth of a child with a genetic or congenital condition.
Finally, we need to appreciate that although these decisions are made by women and couples based on their individual values, the social context in which they are made is important. Conditions such as Down syndrome can lead to significant and profound problems, but they don't always.
We must talk about our attitudes to disability and how we make choices about it. And we should aim for a society that recognises and supports all forms of ability and encourages discussion about our choices.
Ainsley Newson is a senior lecturer in bioethics at the University of Sydney.